Genetics of Intelligence

 “I must have a prodigious quantity of mind; it takes me as much as a week sometimes to make it up.” (Mark Twain)

This page is probably the most difficult one on my blog. But there is a point in any scientific understanding of a subject beyond which popular verbalism simply cannot proceed. A somewhat more technical and quantitative form of expression becomes essential if one is to get even a glimmer of understanding of what the scientists who work in the field are really talking about. I will try to keep the exposition of the genetics of intelligence as basic, simple, and nontechnical as possible, consistent with conveying those ideas most essential for understanding the main themes of this blog.


1- Alfred Binet’s Point of View

I am going to start with an extensive quote taken from Gould’s The Mismeasure of Man, second edition (1996). As I have already explained in this blog, I am not a big fan of Gould because he denies the very concept of intelligence (in Spearman's reification of g, pp. 295-299). This is particularly true in the first edition of The Mismeasure of Man (1981). However, in this excerpt taken from the second edition (Critique of the Bell Curve, pp. 386-390), Gould quotes Binet abundantly, so by quoting Gould here I will be essentially quoting Binet:

“Moreover, Binet feared that if teachers read the IQ number as an inflexible inborn quality, rather than (as he intended) a guide for identifying students in need of help, they would use the scores as a cynical excuse for expunging, rather than aiding, troublesome students. Binet wrote of such teachers: "They seem to reason in the following way: 'Here is an excellent opportunity for getting rid of all the children who trouble us,' and without the true critical spirit, they designate all who are unruly, or disinterested in the school." Binet also feared the powerful bias that has since been labeled "self-fulfilling prophecy" or the Pygmalion effect: if teachers are told that a student is inherently uneducable based on misinterpretation of low IQ scores, they will treat the student as unable, thereby encouraging poor performance by their inadequate nurture, rather than the student's inherent nature. Invoking the case then racking France, Binet wrote:
It is really too easy to discover signs of backwardness in an individual when one is forewarned. This would be to operate as the graphologists did who, when Dreyfus was believed to be guilty, discovered in his handwriting signs of a traitor or a spy.
Binet felt that this test could best be used to identify mild forms of retardation or learning disability. Yet even for such specific and serious difficulties, Binet firmly rejected the idea that his test could identify causes of educational problems, particularly their potential basis in biological inheritance. He only wished to identify children with special needs, so that help could be provided:
Our purpose is to be able to measure the intellectual capacity of a child who is brought to us in order to know whether he is normal or retarded. . . . We shall neglect his etiology, and we shall make no attempt to distinguish between acquired and congenital [retardation]. . . . We do not attempt to establish or prepare a prognosis, and we leave unanswered the question of whether this retardation is curable, or even improvable. We shall limit ourselves to ascertaining the truth in regard to his present mental state.
Binet avoided any claim about inborn biological limits because he knew that an innatist interpretation (which the test scores didn't warrant in any case) would perversely destroy his aim of helping children with educational problems. Binet upbraided teachers who used an assessment of irremediable stupidity to avoid the special effort that difficult students require: "They have neither sympathy nor respect for [these students], and their intemperate language leads them to say such things in their presence as 'This is a child who will never amount to anything . . . he is not intelligent at all.' How often have I heard these imprudent words." In an eloquent passage, Binet then vented his anger against teachers who claim that a student can "never" succeed as a result of inferior biology:
Never! What a momentous word. Some recent thinkers seem to have given their moral support to these deplorable verdicts by affirming that an individual's intelligence is a fixed quantity, a quantity that cannot be increased. We must protest and react against this brutal pessimism; we must try to demonstrate that it is founded upon nothing.
Finally, Binet took pleasure in the successes of teachers who did use his tests to identify students and provide needed help. He defended remedial programs and insisted that gains so recorded must be read as genuine increases in intelligence:
It is in this practical sense, the only one accessible to us, that we say that the intelligence of these children has been increased. We have increased what constitutes the intelligence of a pupil: the capacity to learn and to assimilate instruction.
How tragic and how ironic! If IQ tests had been consistently used as Binet intended, their results would have been entirely beneficent (in this sense, as I stated, I do not oppose mental testing on principle, but only certain versions and philosophies). But the very innatist and antimeliorist spin that Binet had foreseen and decried did become the dominant interpretation, and Binet's intentions were overturned and inverted. And this reversal—the establishment of the hereditarian theory of IQ — occurred in America, not in elitist Europe. The major importers of Binet's method promoted the biodeterminist version that Binet had opposed—and the results continue to ring falsely in our time…
… IQ is a helpful device for identifying children in need of aid, not a dictate of inevitable biology. Such aid can be effective, for the human mind is, above all, flexible. We are not all equal in endowment, and we do not enter the world as blank slates, but most deficiencies can be mediated to a considerable degree, and the palling effect of biological determinism defines its greatest tragedy—for if we give up (because we accept the doctrine of immutable inborn limits), but could have helped, then we have committed the most grievous error of chaining the human spirit.
Why must we follow the fallacious and dichotomous model of pitting a supposedly fixed and inborn biology against the flexibility of training—or nature vs. nurture in the smooth pairing of words that so fixes this false opposition in the public mind? Biology is not inevitable destiny; education is not an assault upon biological limits. Rather, our extensive capacity for educational improvement records a genetic uniqueness vouchsafed only to humans among animals…
Biology is not the enemy of human flexibility, but the source and potentiator (while genetic determinism represents a false theory of biology). Darwinism is not a statement about fixed differences, but the central theory for a discipline—evolutionary biology—that has discovered the sources of human unity in minimal genetic distances among our races and in the geological yesterday of our common origin.”


2- Heredity vs. Heritability

The terms “heredity, hereditary, and inherited” simply mean that a given trait or characteristic of individuals depends on the presence of certain genes or that the gene or genes affecting the trait are transmitted from parents to offspring. Virtually all babies are born with one head, two hands, and ten fingers, for example. As these human characteristics are coded in the genes, they are hereditary characteristics.

According to the National Human Genome Research Institute, we all share 99.9 percent of our three billion DNA base pairs. All human beings are remarkably similar and they always give birth to other human beings (not to whales, cats, or jelly fish). Additionally, humans are far less genetically diverse than most other mammalian species.

The term “heritability” is only applicable (and, in fact, only meaningful) if applied to hereditary characteristics for which the population variance is not zero. When characteristics do not normally vary among individuals, the concept of heritability is simply inapplicable to them. For instance, ears have zero heritability in the human population because all humans have ears. This concept of heritability may seem difficult to grasp but it is not. Let me take an example:

I went to the supermarket the other day with a magnifying glass. I picked randomly two similar bottles of shampoo on a shelf and compared them in detail: I systematically looked for all possible differences. This is what I found:
I first noticed that the level of shampoo in the two bottles was not exactly the same. Also, in one bottle I could see little bubbles but not in the other one. The two tops had not been screwed exactly in the same position; one was headed in one direction while the other was headed in a different direction. Then I took my magnifying glass and found that there were many small scratches all over the two bottles. I started studying the different patterns of scratches: very few of the dozens of scratches on the two bottles were on the same locations. By the time I finished I had established a long and impressive list of differences between the two bottles.
Upon analyzing my data, I discovered that 80% of all the differences between the two bottles were mostly due to scratches uniquely located on one or the other bottle. I called these differences environmental differences (i.e. differences that happened post production and that were mostly due to handling). 20% of the differences I called production differences or differences due to the manufacturing process itself (such as level of liquid or printing variations).

If you think that systematically comparing two similar bottles of shampoo in a supermarket is of little interest (some kind of hair splitting or “fly fucking” as we say in French) you are absolutely right. But this is precisely what heritability aims at doing: finding differences among similar things, differences that MUST BE small because the things compared are similar. For instance, you will never find a heritability study comparing the intelligence of humans and cats because they do not belong to the same species/populations.

Let’s go back to our shampoo bottle example. Knowing that 80% of the variations between my bottles of shampoo are environmental and 20% production based is of absolutely no importance since the two bottles are virtually identical. I will not wash my hair better with one bottle or the other…

You may find some old studies that claim that intelligence is “80% heritable” (the current figures are closer to 40%) and 20% environmental (respectively 60%). This sounds impressive until you realize that the differences are between the tips of very similar icebergs. To make matters worse, the percentages given refer to standard deviation units, which are not real units of intelligence. Last but not least, intelligence is increasing, so the situation is dynamic.

To clarify the situation concerning the heritability of intelligence, I am going to take the example of height. Height is an undisputable measure which, in some essential ways, is very similar to intelligence. There are two crucial differences though:
1- Height is measured on a ratio scale of measurement: a scale with a true zero and equal intervals. So far, the main measures of intelligence are standard deviations, which have no true zero and no equal intervals (we only have the rank orders).
2- The heritability of height is very high and well-known (90%), which is not the case for intelligence.

Interestingly, height was the measure of choice selected by Galton to establish what he first called reversion to the mean and later the law of filial regression to mediocrity (a.k.a. regression to the population mean). An exceptionally tall father, for example, had sons who were shorter than he; and an exceptionally short father had sons who were taller than he.

I have obtained data from the French Army to document what is now known as the secular trend in human growth, maturation, and development. The French Army has sent me the average heights and standard deviations of French conscripts from 1880 to 1990 (French conscription was terminated in the 1990s):

For some unexplained reasons, I haven’t found any serious research that would explain the Flynn effect as a particular case of this broader human growth trend.

I have drawn below the normal curves corresponding to the 1880 and 1990 data (with inches as units for readers unaccustomed to the French metric system).




The average height in 1880 was about 65”, which by today standards would be considered short or very short. The average height in 1990 was about 69”, which by 19th century standards would be considered tall or very tall – only 5% of the 1880 male population had a height equal or higher to 69”. In 1880, very few French males (less than 2%) were taller than 70”, whereas in 1990, 36% of them were. If you consider the number of French males at +1 SD (standard deviation) today (71.5” or roughly the top 16%), i.e. people that can be considered tall, then 99.5% of the 1880 male population was shorter than them. To be at +1 SD in 1880 (considered tall), you had to be 67”. In France, a 71.5” of 1880 was equivalent (in frequency terms) to a 76.5” of 1990. In the US of the 21st century (with an average male height of 69.3” and a SD of 2.94”) a 77.5” man would look like a 71.5” Frenchman of the 19th century.

While heritability may explain the relative height differences between people at a given time, it cannot account for the substantial height increases that took place over more than a century. The height increase was large and almost entirely environmental (because the gene pool of the French population remained basically the same).


Similarly, intelligence could double or triple due to environmental factors and be “90% heritable” (to be clear, the true heritability of intelligence is closer to 40%).

Conclusion 1: If you want to know by how much you can actually increase your IQ, heritability is of no interest at all. Undoubtedly, heritability is an inadequate and misleading indicator that has been overused by hereditarians. Heredity does not determine a fixed level of intelligence, particularly not in the case of human beings who have highly trainable and flexible minds.

Last but not least, intelligence (“general cognitive ability”) is considered by geneticists to be a very polygenic trait, i.e. a characteristic which depends on a great number of genes (it is distributed all over our chromosomes).

Conclusion 2 : You cannot easily “breed” smart human beings, there are far too many genes to manipulate. As Galton had already noticed, eventually, it all reverts to the mean (a mean that luckily seems to be constantly increasing).

If you wish to improve your own IQ, you may contact me (Phil – the author) by clicking on the profile link (above right) or by typing in the following email address: